6
Utilitarianism: A Consequence-Based Approach
Utilitarianism is a form of consequentialism, which entails that the end result (the
“consequence”) should be the most important consideration in any act implemented. The
consequentialist approach, therefore, forms a stark contrast with the deontological
(Universalist) approach discussed earlier, because Universalism focuses on intentions rather
than outcomes while consequentialism, and therefore Utilitarianism, focuses on outcomes
rather than intentions. “[W]hether an act is morally right [in this theory] depends only on
consequences (as opposed to the circumstances or the intrinsic nature of the act or
anything that happens before the act)” (Sinnot-Armstrong, 2011, ¶ 3).
In general, Utilitarianism holds the view that the action that produces the greatest wellbeing
for the largest number is the morally right one. “On the Utilitarian view one ought to
maximize the overall good — that is, consider the good of others as well as one’s own good”
(Driver, 2009, ¶ 2). Using more economic-oriented terms, Robertson, Morris, & Walter
(2007) define Utilitarianism as “a measure of the relative happiness or satisfaction of a
group, usually considered in questions of the allocation of limited resources to a population”
(p. 403). Two of the most noted Utilitarian advocates, Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) and
John Stuart Mill (1806-1873 — a follower of Bentham), felt that “the good” needed to be
maximized to benefit as many stakeholders as possible. Bentham and Mill are considered
the classical Utilitarians. They were major proponents of constructive reforms in the legal
and social realm which explains why they promoted the stance of “the greatest amount of
good for the greatest number” (Driver, ¶ 3). Bentham, for instance, was convinced that
some laws were bad due to their lack of utility which gave rise to mounting societal
despondency without any compensating happiness. He felt, much to the surprise of many of
his contemporaries, that the quality of any act should be measured by its outcomes. This
was, of course, a very instrumental-based mindset, as it was mainly concerned with tangible
results.
Due to Bentham’s focus on the happiness levels of the largest group, there was a significant
degree of flexibility embedded in the Utilitarian approach. After all, whatever is considered a
cause for general happiness today may not be seen as such tomorrow. Tastes, perceptions,
needs, and social constructs change, and “the greatest good for the greatest number” may
look entirely different tomorrow than it does today.
Johnson (2012) posits that there are four steps to conduct a Utilitarian analysis of an ethical
problem: 1) Identifying the issue at hand; 2) Considering all groups, immediate and non-
immediate, that may be affected by this issue; 3) Determining the good and bad
consequences for those involved; and 4) Summing the good and bad consequences and
selecting the option of which the benefits outweigh the costs.
Weiss (2009) emphasizes that there are two types of criteria to be considered in
Utilitarianism: rule-base and act-based. Rule-based Utilitarians consider general rules to
measure the utility of any act, but are not fixated on the act itself. As an example, while a
rule-based Utilitarian may honor the general principle of not-stealing, there may be another
principle under certain circumstances that serve a greater good, thus override this principle.
Act-based Utilitarians consider the value of their act, even though it may not be in line with a
general code of honor. If, for instance, an act-based Utilitarian considers a chemical in his
workplace harmful for a large group of people, he may decide to steal it and discard it,